Critical Responses
1Reflecting on the decisive transition from neo-classical to
Romantic criticism of Shakespeare, Jonathan Bate cites T. S. Eliot's comment
that while we can never be right about Shakespeare, "we should from time
to time change our way of being wrong." Bate's point is that "the
Romantics were especially good at driving out assorted errors of Voltaire and
Dr Johnson with new errors of their own" (Romantics, 3). A
corollary of Eliot's insight is that one benefit of recognizing how Shakespeare
has been understood in the past is to recognize better how we understand him
ourselves. Though more comfortable and seemingly more natural than anything
else, our view is not the right view; it departs from what preceded it but only
at the cost of introducing new distortions that will in turn need to be
corrected. In the process old ideas will be rediscovered and sometimes even repeated,
while genuinely new insights will be introduced. The following discussion of
how Julius Caesar in particular has been interpreted bears out Eliot's
observation and aims to assist understanding of the play by a critical summary
of historical views.
2Criticism of Shakespeare began with a strong bias in favor
of Renaissance Italian neo-classicism whose assumptions continued to dominate
commentary for almost 200 years. Julius Caesar was assessed in light of
criteria supposedly derived from the ancient critics, Aristotle and Horace, and
by those criteria the play was generally found wanting. A reaction against
neo-classical poetry in the late eighteenth century, especially by Wordsworth
and Coleridge, quickly led to a reaction against neo-classical criticism as
well, and Shakespeare emerged as the model of an innovative style. Viewed in
this way, Julius Caesar elicited much greater admiration, especially for
its leading characters, and a debate ensued as to which was in fact the
greatest character—Caesar or Brutus—and why. Character criticism extended into
the early twentieth century with M. W. MacCallum's Shakespeare's Roman Plays
and Their Background, which marked the end of a critical movement, even as
it anticipated some of the twentieth century's most important insights about Julius
Caesar. These included providential imperialism, developed influentially as
the "Tudor myth" by E. M. W. Tillyard, and self-deception, an
informing assumption of postmodern criticism. G. Wilson Knight's The
Imperial Theme moved criticism of Julius Caesar in another
influential direction: the analysis of symbol and theme, which also continues
into postmodern criticism of the play, especially in understanding imagery of
blood and the body.
1. Horace and Julius Caesar
3By a curious and unforeseeable coincidence, the critic who
most strongly influenced the first two centuries of response to Shakespeare's
writing in general, and to Julius Caesar in particular, was a Roman,
Quintus Horatius Flaccus, who turned twenty-one in the year Julius Caesar was
assassinated. Though Shakespeare could hardly have known it, Horace (the Roman
critic's more familiar English name) joined Brutus and Cassius as a young
officer after Julius Caesar's assassination and commanded a legion at the battle
of Philippi in 42 B.C—the concluding event in Shakespeare's play. Eventually
pardoned by Octavian for his opposition, Horace nonetheless withdrew from
political life and became an influential literary figure after the senate
declared Octavian "Augustus" in 27. Thus sidelined from military and
political action, Horace unwittingly set the standard for later interpretation
through a verse epistle, Ars Poetica, which he wrote early in the long
political calm—eventually known as the pax Romana—following Augustus'
defeat of Antony. Centuries later, Italian Renaissance critics came to regard Ars
Poetica as a direct Latin equivalent to Aristotle's Poetics
(Weinberg, 1.111-55), and the prestige of Italian criticism brought Horace to
prominence in early seventeenth-century England. Shakespeare's contemporary,
Ben Jonson rendered Horace's poem in English (published in 1640), probably from
a copy of the Ars Poetica he owned in Latin, bound together with the
Italian commentary of Bernardino Parthenio (1560), with "much of the
second part . . . underlined" (Jonson, ed. Herford and Simpson, 1.266).
(On Parthenio, see Weinberg, 1.145-47.) Moreover, Jonson largely followed Ars
Poetica in the brief comments he penned on his fellow actor and
playwright—the first critical response to Shakespeare and the first of many to
interpret Shakespeare through a Renaissance Horatian lens.
4One of Jonson's most Horatian passages appears in his
commendatory verses for the Folio of 1623, "To the Memory of My Beloved,
the Author, Mr. William Shakespeare," where Jonson acknowledges both
nature and art in Shakespeare's writing. After praising nature, Jonson turns to
art with emphasis:
5Yet must I not give nature all; thy art,
My gentle Shakespeare, must enjoy a part.
For though the poet's matter nature be,
His art doth give the fashion; and that he
Who casts to write a living line must sweat
(Such as thine are) and strike the second heat
Upon the muse's anvil; turn the same,
And himself with it, and that he thinks to frame,
Or for the laurel he may gain a scorn;
For a good poet's made as well as born. (55-64)
My gentle Shakespeare, must enjoy a part.
For though the poet's matter nature be,
His art doth give the fashion; and that he
Who casts to write a living line must sweat
(Such as thine are) and strike the second heat
Upon the muse's anvil; turn the same,
And himself with it, and that he thinks to frame,
Or for the laurel he may gain a scorn;
For a good poet's made as well as born. (55-64)
6Horace's way of treating the topos of art vs. nature
was especially influential in the Renaissance, and Jonson is indebted to Ars
Poetica. The awkward parenthesis, "(Such as thine are)," in
"To the Memory" (60) is deliberate. Referring back to "living
line" (59), it inevitably refers to "sweat" as well, which it
immediately follows—as if Jonson is saying that Shakespeare had to sweat out
his lines. Indeed, that is precisely Jonson's claim, once the tangled syntax is
straightened out: poetry did not come to Shakespeare merely by nature; he had
to work for it, "For a good poet's made as well as born." Jonson's
image of "the muse's anvil" is from Horace: "to the anvil bring
/ Those ill-turned verses to new hammering," in Jonson's translation
(Herford and Simpson, 8.304-37, lines 627-8; 440-1 in the original Latin). That
Shakespeare did not sweat or hammer out his verse on the anvil enough is
a backhanded compliment in the commendatory poem, like the often-quoted
qualifying clause, "though thou hadst small Latin and less Greek"
(31). Horace's advice to Roman poets lies behind this clause: "Take you
the Greek examples for your light / In hand, and turn them over, day and
night" (396-7; 268-9). If Shakespeare had followed Horace's advice, Jonson
implies, Shakespeare's poetry would have achieved a better balance between
nature and art.
7Horace's comments on nature and art underlie Jonson's other
extended critical comment on Shakespeare, in which he mentions Julius Caesar
in particular. According to William Drummond of Hawthornden, Jonson complained
that "Shakespeare wanted [i.e., lacked] art" (Herford and Simpson,
1.133), and the complaint explains Jonson's reminiscence in Discoveries
(1640):
8His wit was in his own power; would the rule of it had been
so too. Many times he fell into those things could not escape laughter, as when
he said in the person of Caesar (one speaking to him, "Caesar, thou dost
me wrong"), he replied, "Caesar did never wrong but with just
cause" and such like, which were ridiculous. (Herford and Simpson, 8.584)
9Jonson uses "wit" in this passage with full
awareness of its Latin counterpart, ingenium, meaning something like
"imaginative intelligence," which places it in the domain of nature,
rather than art, and his usage therefore anticipates the high neo-classical
contrast between "wit" and "judgment" (Lewis, 90-96). His
point about undisciplined wit in Julius Caesar refers to the moments
before Caesar's assassination, when Caesar refuses Metellus Cimber's appeal on
behalf of his brother, Publius Cimber. As printed in the Folio, Caesar
concludes his refusal with a self-righteous assertion: "Know, Caesar doth
not wrong, nor without cause / Will he be satisfied" (TLN 1254-5). Jonson
remembered that Metellus had objected, "Caesar, thou dost me wrong,"
to which Caesar had replied, "Caesar did never wrong but with just
cause." In the late eighteenth century, Thomas Tyrwhitt conjecturally
reconstructed Caesar's lines as Jonson might have heard them: "Know Caesar
doth not wrong, but with just cause, / Nor without cause will he be
satisfied" (Steevens 2, 8.59n. 1). Tyrwhitt surmised that Jonson's
criticism of the lines had reached Shakespeare, who undertook to rewrite them
in response before publication of Julius Caesar in the Folio.
10For present purposes, the point of Jonson's critique is its
Horatian spirit, not the accuracy of Jonson's memory. (For further comments on
that point, see the Textual Introduction). Jonson alludes to Horace again in
his reminiscence to Drummond: "I remember the players have often mentioned
it as an honor to Shakespeare that in his writing, whatsoever he penned, he never
blotted out line. My answer hath been, 'Would he had blotted a thousand,'"
citing the line from Julius Caesar as an instance. Jonson borrowed the
metaphor of blotting from Horace, whose lines he had translated: "If you
denied you had no better strain, / And twice or thrice had 'ssayed it, still in
vain, / He'd bid, blot all" (625-27; 439-40). Jonson's whole critique of
Shakespeare in Discoveries makes sense in light of the way Jonson had
translated Horace's advice:
11A wise and honest man will cry out shame
On artless verse; the hard ones he will blame,
Blot out the careless with his turnèd pen,
Cut off superflouous ornaments, and when
They're dark, bid "Clear this," all that's doubtful wrote
Reprove, and what is to be changèd note,
Become an Aristarchus, and not say,
"Why should I grieve my friend this trifling way?"
These trifles into mischiefs lead,
The man once mocked and suffered wrong to tread. (633-42; 445-52)
On artless verse; the hard ones he will blame,
Blot out the careless with his turnèd pen,
Cut off superflouous ornaments, and when
They're dark, bid "Clear this," all that's doubtful wrote
Reprove, and what is to be changèd note,
Become an Aristarchus, and not say,
"Why should I grieve my friend this trifling way?"
These trifles into mischiefs lead,
The man once mocked and suffered wrong to tread. (633-42; 445-52)
12Aristarchus, a second-century B.C.E. Alexandrian and scholar
of Homer, was famous for his incisive criticism, and Jonson images himself as
such a critic to Shakespeare, assuming the Horatian persona of the supportive
but alert reader—one whose art was required to curb the other's prolific nature
(Martindale). If the players had not actually commended Shakespeare in the way
Jonson claims they did, he would have had to invent them to create for himself
the Horatian role he loved to play.
13Jonson was the first swallow in the spring of neo-classical
criticism of Shakespeare on Horatian principles. For two centuries after
Jonson, critics of Shakespeare positioned themselves on a Horatian continuum according
to their preference for nature or art. Flatly contradicting Jonson's
commendatory verses for the Folio that "a good poet's made as well as
born," Leonard Digges asserts that "Poets are born, not made" in
the opening line of his commendatory verses for Shakespeare's Poems
(1640; Vickers 1.27-29), citing Shakespeare as proof that nature is more
important than art. Digges thus originated in English an idea that was much
later Latinized for the first time by Coleridge (Ringler 197n. 1). To make the
point about Shakespeare, Digges compares him with Jonson, allusively
contrasting Jonson's published Works (1616) with Shakespeare's book of
poems, "where thou hast (I will not say, / Reader, his works—for to
contrive a play / To him was none) the pattern of all wit, / Art without art
unparalleled as yet" (7-10). Nature enabled Shakespeare to
"play," not "work," Digges claims, and thereby to achieve
the highest art—a commendation that has some similarities with Polixenes'
evaluation of art and nature in The Winter's Tale (4.4.89-97), which is
closer to Puttenham's Art of English Poesie (1589), as Harold Wilson
argues, than to Horace. Digges subsequently contrasts Shakespeare and Jonson
again with specific reference to Julius Caesar:
14So have I seen, when Caesar would appear,
And on the stage at half-sword parley were
Brutus and Cassius, oh, how the audience
Were ravished, with what wonder they went thence. (41-44)
And on the stage at half-sword parley were
Brutus and Cassius, oh, how the audience
Were ravished, with what wonder they went thence. (41-44)
15This, in contrast to Jonson's classical tragedies:
16When some new day they would not brook a line
Of tedious (though well-labored) Catiline.
Sejanus too was irksome; they prized more
Honest Iago or the jealous Moor. (45-48)
Of tedious (though well-labored) Catiline.
Sejanus too was irksome; they prized more
Honest Iago or the jealous Moor. (45-48)
17"Well-labored" is a backhanded tribute to Jonson's
art in his two classically correct and learnedly glossed tragedies. They are
indeed "works," Digges implies, suggesting that Jonson had sweated at
the anvil of the muses for too long.
18Digges had been thinking about these issues for several
years. His commendatory verses for Shakespeare's Poems in 1640 twice
echo his earlier commendatory verses for the Folio of 1623: "half-sword
parley" and "wit-fraught book." His praise of Shakespeare as
"the pattern of all wit" uses "wit" in the same way Jonson
uses it but draws the opposite conclusion—not that Shakespeare's wit needed
curbing but that it was a model to every poet. Digges thus anticipates Milton's
contrast in "L'Allegro" (1631) between "Jonson's learned
sock" and "sweetest Shakespeare, fancy's child / Warbl[ing] his
native woodnotes wild" (132-4). Milton uses "fancy" to mean much
the same thing Jonson and Digges mean by "wit" and thereby attributes
Shakespeare's skill, again, to nature rather than art.
19Less combative than Digges, Margaret Cavendish drew on
Horace to defend Shakespeare's characters in particular. "So well he hath
expressed in his plays all sorts of persons," Cavendish writes, "as
one would think he had been transformed into every one of those persons he hath
described" (Vickers, 1.43). Taken alone, this praise might be misconstrued
as an assertion of imaginative identification on a Romantic model, but
Cavendish wrote in 1662, and what she has in mind is Horace's admonition
concerning the decorum of character, in Jonson's somewhat opaque translation:
"Or follow fame, thou that dost write, or feign / Things in themselves
agreeing" (169-70; 119-20). Jonson aimed to capture Horace's point about
self-consistency, as the translator's subsequent lines make clear:
20If something strange that never yet was had
Unto the scene thou bring'st, and dar'st create
A mere new person, look he keep his state
Unto the last, as when he first went forth,
Still to be like himself, and hold his worth. (178-82; 125-7)
Unto the scene thou bring'st, and dar'st create
A mere new person, look he keep his state
Unto the last, as when he first went forth,
Still to be like himself, and hold his worth. (178-82; 125-7)
21"Keep his state" and "hold his worth"
accurately reflect Horace's concern with identity conceived in broadly stoic
and social-class terms (Miles 31)—a point Cavendish makes in defending
Shakespeare's "ingenious" and "witty" ability to create
compelling clowns as well as kings (Vickers 1.42). The poet's aim should be to
keep each character "like himself," in Jonson's translation—consistent,
that is, with expectation as established by the classical three levels of style
(high, middle, and low) in their presumed decorous correspondence to levels of
society. Jonson himself construed this expectation differently, as his plays
make clear, avoiding the mingling of social classes that is one of
Shakespeare's hallmarks. Jonson, in short, would not have agreed with
Cavendish, and later neo-classical critics agreed with Jonson.
22Whereas Horace cites examples of self-consistent characters
from classical epic and tragedy, Cavendish cites examples from Shakespeare,
singling out those in Julius Caesar for particular admiration: "Certainly
Julius Caesar, Augustus Caesar, and Antonius did never really act their parts
better, if so well, as he hath described them, and I believe that Antonius and
Brutus did not speak better to the people than he hath feigned them"
(Vickers 1.43). Cavendish's praise of Shakespeare's characterization as
"witty" and "ingenious" identifies it as the product of
nature, rather than art, yet Cavendish argues that Shakespeare's characters
meet Horace's requirements of artful self-consistency ("act their
parts"). Her praise, in short, is very close to Digges's, without
challenging Jonson as forthrightly as Digges had.
23By the later seventeenth century, the Italian Renaissance
conflation of Horace with Aristotle had become a widespread critical assumption
in England: "Of that book which Aristotle hath left us," wrote John
Dryden in 1668, "Horace his Art of Poetry is an excellent comment,
and, I believe, restores to us that second book of his concerning comedy, which
is wanting in him" (An Essay of Dramatic Poesie, Works
17.17). Horace was so familiar to Dryden that he seems to have quoted Ars
Poetica from memory, judging from the slight alterations he sometimes
introduces (Hammond). As a practicing dramatist himself, Dryden could not help
admiring Shakespeare and others in "the giant race before the flood"
(i.e., the dramatists before the civil war), as he writes in "To My Dear
Friend, Mr. Congreve" (line 5; Works 4.432), but he was aware that
the "giants" did not conform to neo-classical theory, and he was
therefore inclined to defend them as inspired more by nature than by art.
Indeed, Dryden's allusion to the "giant race" may actually be as arch
as it is appreciative, judging from an allusion to the same giants thirty years
earlier, in Astraea Redux, written to celebrate the coronation of
Charles II. There Dryden had impugned anti-Royalists as antediluvian giants,
who "own'd a lawless savage liberty / Like that our painted ancestors so
priz'd / Ere empire's arts their breasts had civiliz'd" (lines 46-8, Works
1.23). The contrast between "savage liberty" and imperial
"arts" is a political judgment informed by the esthetic contrast
between nature and art, and given Dryden's consistent political conservatism,
the same judgment still seems to cling to Dryden's much later allusion to
giants, including Shakespeare.
24As the best of seventeenth-century critics, it is
unfortunate that Dryden had little to say about Julius Caesar. (Some
editors ascribe the prologue to a Restoration revival of Julius Caesar
to Dryden [Vickers 1.141], and the ascription has in its favor the poem's
praise of "artless beauty" that "lies in Shakespeare's
wit.") Writing about himself in the third person, as Jonson habitually
does in his dramatic prologues, Dryden glances allusively at the quarrel
between Brutus and Cassius (4.3) in the Prologue to Aureng-Zebe,
acknowledging his awe at Shakespeare's "nature," which nonetheless
lacks art:
25But spite of all his pride, a secret shame
Invades his breast at Shakespear's sacred name:
Aw'd, when he hears his Godlike Romans rage,
He, in a just despair, would quit the Stage;
And to an Age less polish'd, more unskill'd,
Does, with disdain, the foremost Honours yield. (Works 12.159)
Invades his breast at Shakespear's sacred name:
Aw'd, when he hears his Godlike Romans rage,
He, in a just despair, would quit the Stage;
And to an Age less polish'd, more unskill'd,
Does, with disdain, the foremost Honours yield. (Works 12.159)
26If Dryden had written about Julius Caesar at greater
length, he would likely have praised the plot, despite its failure to achieve
the three "unities" of time, place, and action that were prized by
Italian theorists and French dramatists, but Dryden would almost certainly have
decried the mingling of plebeians with patricians, because it was perceived to
violate Horatian decorum of character: "each subject should retain / The
place allotted it, with decent thews" (124-25; 89). (Jonson uses
"thews" to mean "traits" or "attributes," and he
knew that "decent" and "decorous" have the same Latin
root.) If Dryden had written a version of the play, it would almost certainly
have had no commoners, i.e., no witty Cobbler, no rowdy plebeians, and no
Lucius.
27While trying to refine the rude manners of pre-Restoration
drama in his own plays, i.e., to create more artful drama, Dryden was also
trying to protect himself from the judgment of a strict neo-classical critic,
Thomas Rymer, whose censure of Julius Caesar is included in his Short
View of Tragedy (1693). Dryden clearly stated his disagreement with Rymer
in his draft "Heads of an Answer to Rymer," including notes for
replying to Rymer's earlier book, The Tragedies of the Last Age Considered
and Examined (1678), but the notes remained unpublished (Works
17:185-93). Rymer was formidable not only for the narrow certitude of his
theory but even more for his vituperative style. With Horace's decorum of
character in mind, Rymer heaped scorn on the indignity with which Shakespeare
"treats the noblest Romans. But there is no other cloth in his wardrobe.
Everyone must be content to wear a fool's coat who comes to be dressed by
him" (156). This reverses Margaret Cavendish's assessment and outflanks
the objection that Shakespeare mingles patricians and plebeians by denying
noble status even to his patricians. "For indeed that language which
Shakespeare puts in the mouth of Brutus would not suit or be convenient unless
from some son of the shambles or some natural off-spring of the butchery"
(151). So indignant is Rymer with Shakespeare on the question of character
decorum that he does not even address Shakespeare's violation of the three
unities. He reserves that censure for Jonson's Catiline, which he also
savages: as a classically trained playwright, Jonson should have known better
(161). Rymer's view of art was so extreme and so narrow that it denied any art
to Shakespeare, asserting that he drew ignorantly on nothing but nature and his
own commoner's imagination, which "was still running after his masters,
the cobblers, and parish clerks, and Old Testament strollers" (156).
28Rymer's critical indignation had a large moral component,
which he derived (or at any rate justified) from Horace's admonition that the
best fictions mix "doctrine" (utile) with "delight"
(dulci) (Ars Poetica 516; 360). Rymer was the first to infer that
"doctrine" specifically required "poetic justice," that is,
a presumed vindication of divine providence in a tragic plot by allotting a
benign fortune to moral characters and a malign outcome to immoral ones. Using
Rymer's criterion, all of Shakespeare's tragedies are failures, as John Dennis
argued vigorously, if narrowly, concerning the "irreligious" Julius
Caesar in particular. The killing of Caesar must be either "a murder
or a lawful action." If it is lawful, then the deaths of Brutus and
Cassius "are downright murder." But if Caesar's death is murder, then
Brutus and Cassius "are justly punished for it," and Shakespeare is
wrong not to show the other conspirators being punished as well, "which
proceeding gives an occasion to the people to draw a dangerous inference from
it, which may be destructive to government and to human society" (Vickers
2.147). Charles Gildon combined a critique of poetic justice in Julius
Caesar with a complaint about its plot. "Brutus is plainly the shining
and darling character of the poet," so the play is faulty either in its
title or in not ending with Caesar's death, which would have made it "much
more regular, natural, and beautiful. But then the moral must naturally have
been the punishment or ill success of tyranny" (Vickers 2.256).
29No less Horatian (in the neo-classical view of Horace) are
Dennis's comments about Shakespeare's classical learning, which also address
the question of the play's length and focus. Jonson's slighting remark about
Shakespeare's "small Latin and less Greek" was inspired by Horace's
admonition to Latin poets to steep themselves in Greek models, and in turn it
seems to have inspired Dennis to claim that the failures of Julius Caesar
are attributable to deficiencies in Shakespeare's classical learning: "Had
Shakespeare read either Sallust or Cicero how could he have made so very little
of the first and greatest of men, as that Caesar should be but a fourth-rate
actor in his own tragedy?" (Vickers 2.288). Dennis certainly knew that
Shakespeare drew his inspiration from Plutarch, so Dennis's complaint has less
to do with Shakespeare's lack of reading than with his not reading the sources
Dennis thought he should have read in order to write the play that Dennis
thought he should have written. Applying similar strictures, Gildon complained
that Julius Caesar failed to conform to the "unity of action, which
can never be broke without destroying the poem." The play should have
ended with Caesar's death; otherwise, the ending is arbitrary, and having thus
failed to observe one unity, the play fails to observe others: "Natural
reason indeed showed to Shakespeare the absurdity of making the representation
longer than the time and the place more extensive than the place of
acting" (Vickers 2.222). Awed by Rymer's extreme neo-classicism, Dennis
and Gildon show how critical reason became increasingly naturalized to the
particular strictures that critics had learned to associate with Horace and
Aristotle.
30The topics of the Horatian debate concerning Julius
Caesar were thus well established in England by the early eighteenth
century, and high neo-classical criticism repeated those topics with
variations. Critics who believed art should follow putatively Horatian and
Aristotelian rules found Shakespeare's departure from the rules a problem in Julius
Caesar, as Dennis and Gildon had. In this category are failures in the
decorum of character (imagining plebeians in the same play with patricians; not
making patricians speak and act like patricians) and violations of the three
unities, especially the failure to unify action and time. If the play ended
with the death of Caesar, it would be very nearly continuous in time over the
course of not much more than twenty-four hours, and it would not entail
"extraneous" action involving Brutus's defeat, as well as Caesar's.
Shakespeare's failure to meet the requirements of art was due, moreover, to his
ignorance of classical models—his failure to study Greek and Latin as
assiduously as his critics had.
31On the other side, neo-classical defenders of Julius
Caesar also used Horace as their authority, arguing that nature was
Shakespeare's inspiration, rather than art, and thereby following (whether they
knew it or not) the example of Leonard Digges. "Nature" came
increasingly to mean not only superior imaginative intelligence, described as
"wit" or "genius," but also an ability to understand and
convey the feelings of characters and even the advantage derived from
Shakespeare's being a relatively unlearned countryman. Richard Steele conceded
in 1709 that Shakespeare introduces Julius Caesar in his nightgown, but this
shows that "genius was above . . . mechanic methods of showing
greatness" (Vickers 2.205). Shakespeare depicts the "great soul"
debating subjects of ultimate importance, "without endeavoring to
prepossess his audience with empty show and pomp." What would have been a
scandal to Rymer is a stroke of genius to Steele. One of Shakespeare's best
early editors, Lewis Theobald, maintained that "particular
irregularities" in Shakespeare do not matter, because "it is not to
be expected that a genius like Shakespeare should be judged by the laws of
Aristotle and the other prescribers to the stage" (Vickers 2.308).
Theobald defends the quarrel of Brutus and Cassius by comparing it to
aristocratic quarrels in Iphigenia by Euripides and in The Maid's
Tragedy (1610) by John Fletcher, who had been generally regarded as more
artful than Shakespeare since Dryden first said he was. Of the three, Theobald
concludes, Shakespeare's treatment is "incomparably the best."
Alexander Pope defended Shakespeare against the charge of being unlearned,
observing that in Julius Caesar "not only the spirit but manners of
the Romans are exactly drawn" (Vickers 2.407). Still, in his own edition
of Julius Caesar Pope printed a dash for the word "hats" in
the line, "their hats are plucked about their ears" (TLN 697),
because Pope believed Roman patricians wore no hats. Theobald rejected the
"hiatus" as "hypercritical": "Surely we make mad work
with this or any other of our author's plays did we attempt to try them so
strictly by the touchstone of antiquity" (Vickers 2.460).
32The most thoughtful and incisive neo-classical defense of
Shakespeare as "the poet of nature" was by Samuel Johnson, in the
preface to his edition of Shakespeare (1765). Johnson used the phrase to mean
that Shakespeare "holds up to his readers a faithful mirror of manners and
of life" (7.62). Developing an argument he had first tried almost fifteen
years earlier (Vickers 3.434), Johnson wittily and cogently demolished
arguments for the unities of time and place (7.76-80) and asserted that
Shakespeare "has well enough preserved the unity of action," in that
his plays have discernible beginnings and middles, "and the end of the
play is the end of expectation" (7.75). To be sure, Johnson finds fault
with Shakespeare, and in this he follows neo-classical precedent, starting with
Dryden, though Johnson's most influential example was Henry Home, Lord Kames
(Vickers 4.471-97). Indeed, Johnson enumerates faults in Shakespeare that are
"sufficient to obscure and overwhelm any other merit" (7.71-74).
Among them is the violation of poetic justice: "he makes no just
distribution of good or evil, nor is always careful to show in the virtuous a
disapprobation of the wicked; he carried his persons indifferently through
right and wrong, and at the close dismisses them without further care, and
leaves their examples to operate by chance" (7.71).
33This echo of Rymer repeats the familiar neo-classical
complaint that Shakespeare lacked art, so it is hardly surprising that
"nature" and "natural" recur throughout Johnson's preface
as terms of guarded praise. Shakespeare's "adherence to general nature has
exposed him to the censure of critics who form their judgments upon narrower
principles" (7.65); Shakespeare "indulged his natural
inclination"; comedy was "a mode of thinking congenial to his
nature"; his characters "are natural, and therefore durable";
"his characters are praised as natural" (7.69-70); "his power
was the power of nature" (7.73). Johnson is not far removed, in his
assessment of Shakespeare and "nature," from Margaret Cavendish: both
critics draw ultimately on Horace and on the decorum of character in
particular. Closer in time to Johnson, a similar position had been staked out
by Gildon in 1703: "But if [poets] would study nature as much as
Shakespeare did, their errors would be less visible and more supportable. But
there is nothing more familiar with the ignorant decriers of the rules than to
instance Shakespeare's pleasing without them, as in his characters, passions,
etc.—the rules being only nature methodized—for sure nobody (I mean of sense) ever
admired his conduct, the rules of which not being known in his time is his best
plea for his offenses against them" (Vickers 2.8-9).
34Still, Johnson's Horatian thinking about Shakespeare and
"nature" goes beyond character to include what might be called
"untrained originality." "The English nation, in the time of
Shakespeare, was yet struggling to emerge from barbarity" (7.81), Johnson
believed, so for Shakespeare "the greater part of his excellence was the
product of his own genius" (7.87), since he lacked the example of art.
Johnson was easily persuaded by the conventional neo-classical argument that
Shakespeare was "natural" in the same way as Homer: "Perhaps it
would not be easy to find any author except Homer who invented as much as
Shakespeare, who so much advanced the studies which he cultivated, or effused
so much novelty upon his age or country" (7.90). With "genius"
as the explanation of Shakespeare's accomplishment, Johnson's summary judgment
about Julius Caesar in particular is easier to understand. Johnson was
not moved by the play, and he therefore thought it exhibited less of
Shakespeare's natural gifts than other tragedies did: "his adherence to
the real story and to Roman manners seems to have impeded the natural vigor of
his genius" (8.836). As the great poet of nature, in Johnson's estimation,
Shakespeare did less well when it came to classical material, with its greater
suitability to treatment as art, in which Shakespeare was deficient.
2. Romantic Julius Caesar
35The straitjacket that neo-classical critics had tied around
themselves by means of Horace and Aristotle was at last thrown off by critics
writing under the influence of Romanticism in the early nineteenth century. To
be sure, neo-classical criticism is subtler and more various than Romantic
critics made it out to be for their own polemical purposes, and their
innovations sometimes seem continuous with it. Leonard Digges's deliberately
anti-Horatian (and anti-Jonsonian) assertion that "Poets are born, not
made" was given Latin form for the first time by S. T. Coleridge in the
early nineteenth century: "Poeta nascitur, non fit" (Bate, Romantics
148; Ringler, "Poeta" 497). Moreover, the "organic
form" championed by both A. W. von Schlegel and Coleridge was arguably a
carry-over from neo-classical criticism—an attempt to assert unity in
Shakespeare's plays where the three neo-classical unities were manifestly
inapplicable. Again, the character criticism that became a hallmark of Romantic
commentary had been anticipated by Margaret Cavendish, as noted above. Still,
unlike Digges, Coleridge was not reacting against Jonson in his declaration
about the poet being born, not made (though he undoubtedly knew the Horatian
allusion, he had something else entirely in mind); the assertion of organic
unity was not merely a repeated commonplace but was so new and so persuasive
that it persisted as a critical assumption until the second half of the
twentieth century; and the new character criticism was much more than
Cavendish's variation on the Horatian decorum of character. In short, Romantic
critics set off in a genuinely new direction, which made an impact on the
understanding of Julius Caesar, as well as other plays.
36The new direction was marked by character criticism in
particular, which became the favored means of understanding Shakespeare's plays
until well into the twentieth century. "The unity of character pervades
the whole of his dramas," Coleridge asserted, closely linking character
with "the unity of feeling," in deliberate contrast to the
neo-classical three unities (Bate, Romantics 129), which represent
merely mechanical coherence, imposed from without, rather than "organic
form" (128). Schlegel had earlier offered a version of this distinction
(4-5), as Coleridge duly acknowledges. The Romantics were probably not indebted
to Steele's contrast, noted above, between Shakespeare's "genius" and
"mechanic methods," but Steele's comment suggests greater continuity
between neo-classical and Romantic assumptions than the Romantics themselves
wished to acknowledge. Coleridge applied his idea most influentially to Hamlet,
where he saw the character of the Prince driving events, so that character
actually determined the form of the play (136-7). "In all his
[Shakespeare's] various characters," Coleridge observes, in his clearest
linking between character and organic form, "we still feel ourselves
communing with the same human nature, which is every where present as the
vegetable sap in the branches, sprays, buds, blossoms, and fruits, their
shapes, tastes, and odours" (159-60).
37The consequence of Shakespeare's "communing . . . with
human nature," in Coleridge's estimation, is that Shakespeare was
"myriad-minded" (147, 156), a point that especially impressed Hazlitt
in his own assessment of Shakespeare's characters. In this point, too,
Coleridge and Hazlitt were preceded by Schlegel, who observes of Shakespeare
that "It is the capability of transporting himself so completely into
every situation, even the most unusual, that he is enabled, as the plenipotentiary
of the whole human race, without particular instructions for each separate
case, to act and speak in the name of every individual" (97). Shakespeare
"seemed scarcely to have an individual existence of his own,"
Hazzlitt maintains, "but to borrow that of others at will, and to pass
successively through 'every variety of untried being'" (166). "Each
of his characters is as much itself, and as absolutely independent of the rest,
as well as of the author, as if they were living persons, not fictions of the
mind" (184). Margaret Cavendish had exclaimed of Shakespeare that
"one would think he had been transformed into every one of those persons
he hath described," and Hazlitt makes a similar claim: "The poet may
be said, for the time, to identify himself with the character he wishes to
represent, and to pass from one to another, like the same soul successively
animating different bodies" (184). The difference is that Cavendish was
thinking in terms of Horatian character decorum, while Hazlitt was thinking of Romantic
feeling and the animating force of character in a plot that is
character-driven. Even when Shakespeare imagines a wholly new character, like
Caliban, Hazlitt argues, he creates a unified world around the character, and
that world is the play's unity. "The whole 'coheres semblably together' in
time, place, and circumstance" (182). In this point, too, Schlegel
anticipated Hazlitt—even in using Caliban as an example: "These beings,
though existing only in the imagination, nevertheless possess such truth and
consistency, that even with such misshapen abortions as Caliban, he extorts the
assenting conviction, that were such beings they would so conduct
themselves" (98).
38Though the Romantics' emphasis on character was continuous
with neo-classical admiration for Shakespeare's characters, the Romantic
argument linking characterization to a new conception of unity in the plays was
genuinely innovative and influential. Indeed, it is still evident in the New
Variorum Edition of Julius Caesar, published in 1913, which devotes the
first two-thirds of its critical summary to "The Character of Caesar"
and "The Character of Brutus" (386-420). Schlegel pointed the way in
this direction with his declaration that "Caesar is not the hero of the
piece, but Brutus" (Bate, Romantics 374), a point on which critics
differed repeatedly, setting off a debate about the "hero" of the
play. Neo-classical critics had noticed the imbalance of attention to Brutus in
Julius Caesar (see Gildon's comment above, for example, that
"Brutus is plainly the shining and darling character of the poet"),
but the debate reflected in the New Variorum is rooted in nineteenth-century
character criticism. Coleridge was frankly puzzled by Brutus: "I do not at
present see into Shakespeare's motive, his rationale, or in what point of view
he meant Brutus' character to appear" (Bate, Romantics 375).
Hazlitt, however, thought "the whole design of the conspirators to
liberate their country fails from the generous temper and overweening confidence
of Brutus in the goodness of their cause and the assistance of others"
(377)—in other words, Brutus's character drives the plot. William Watkiss Lloyd
agreed that "it is Brutus on whom the interest and sympathy of the play
converge and become continuous throughout its course, making him thus, in a
certain sense, its hero" (Variorium 387), and Gustav Freytag agreed:
"Brutus, the warm-hearted youth, the noble, the patriotic, is hero"
(Variorium 427). "It is indeed true," echoed H. N. Hudson, "that
Brutus is the hero" (234).
39Georg Gottfried Gervinus, argued, on the contrary, that the
play "does not bear [Caesar's] name without a reason," because the
civil war that commences with his death is carried on in his name (721), and
variations on Gervinus' argument were offered by Albert Lindner and Edward
Dowden. "As Caesar lives, he is a weakling," wrote Lindner, "a
phantom with many infirmities; after his death, a spiritual power, more fearful
than even in life" (Variorum 387). Dowden cited the acknowledgment of
Antony, Cassius, and Brutus in Julius Caesar concerning the posthumus
power of Caesar and concluded that "With strict propriety, therefore, the
play bears the name of Julius Caesar" (288). These comments by no means
settled the long-running debate; they merely illustrate how the debate
originated in the Romantic assumption that the characters of Shakespeare's
plays are the most important thing about them.
40The Romantics linked an innovative notion of dramatic unity
not only to their emphasis on character but also to an idea about purpose in
history that affected their criticism of Julius Caesar in particular,
because Shakespeare's best known Roman play was thought to anticipate the
historical teleology that Romantics themselves believed. Their own self-designation,
"Romantic," derives from an understanding of European history that
distinguished the "classic" heritage of Greece and Rome from the
Germanic heritage that replaced it. Aiming to distinguish the supposedly
timeless rules of neo-classical "art" from the art he admired,
Coleridge constructed a polemical history of Europe based on the commonplace
that Latinate Germanic languages were called "romance" languages,
"to which term, as distinguishing their Songs and Fabliaux, we owe the
word and the species of romance—the romantic may be considered as
opposed to the antique, and from this change of manners, those of Shakespear
take their colouring. He is not to be tried by ancient and classic rules, but
by the standard of his age. That law of unity which has its foundation, not in
factitious necessity of custom, but in nature herself, is instinctively
observed by Shakespear" (Bate, Romantics 129).
41In short, the reason Coleridge thought that the mechanical
rules of neo-classical criticism were inapplicable to an artist like
Shakespeare is that Shakespeare fulfilled the purpose of history by drawing on
his "romantic" heritage. Schlegel similarly understood Jonson's
Horatian response to Shakespeare not only as Leonard Digges had understood it
but also as essentially foreign to Shakespeare: "Ben Jonson, a younger
contemporary and rival of Shakespeare, who laboured in the sweat of his brow,
but with no great success, to expel the romantic drama from the English stage,
and to form it on the model of the ancients, gave it as his opinion that
Shakespeare did not blot enough, and that as he did not possess much
school-learning, he owed more to nature than to art" (Bate, Romantics
89). Hazlitt agreed that neo-classical critics "made criticism a kind of
Procrustes' bed of genius"—Shakespeare's genius, in particular (Bate, Romantics
177). Behind this view is an unstated idea of history itself unfolding
organically, with the "romantic," personified by Shakespeare,
inevitably supplanting the "classic," despite the attempts of critics
from Ben Jonson to Samuel Johnson to resist the supplanting by defining art
narrowly in Horatian terms. Only with the Romantics had Shakespeare come into
his own as the perfect flowering of English culture. "O what great men
hast thou not produced," exclaimed Coleridge, "England! my country!
truly indeed—" (Bate, Romantics 152).
42The Romantics' triumphalist idea of history has some
continuity with the Enlightenment idea of progress, but it took on a life of
its own, not only informing literary criticism but also anticipating
nineteenth-century nationalism (as Coleridge's exclamation suggests),
opposition to French cultural hegemony with attendant memories and fears of
political rivalry (Bate, Romantics 10-13, 16-20, 24-25), the music of
Richard Wagner, much of Tennyson's poetry, and even the teleology of biological
and social evolution. The idea affected criticism of Julius Caesar in
that Shakespeare was thought by some Romantics to have divined the
nineteenth-century idea of history in his Roman history play. "One and the
same thought is reflected by the fall of Caesar," wrote Hermann Ulrici,
"in the deaths of Brutus and Cassius, and in the victory of Antony and
Octavius," and this "thought" is "the course of history"
(Variorum 429-30). Caesar was really overthrown not by the conspiracy but by a
disembodied "oligarchical principle," represented by the triumvirate
that replaced the conspirators. "It conquered because it had the right of
the immediate present on its side" (430). Such an understanding of history
sees whatever happens as happening by necessity, as the inevitable unfolding of
an irresistible process, which produces "the right of the immediate
present." Hegel's influence on this conception may be operating in D. J.
Snider's claim that "Caesar is the real hero" in Julius Caesar
because he represents the "World Spirit" that finally triumphs:
though opposed by Cassius, it is ultimately vindicated by "the restoration
and absolute validity of the Caesarian movement" (Variorum, 432).
"Spirit" is Hegel's term for historical movements, and Snider may
have been thinking in quasi-Hegelian terms, seeing Caesar's thesis as opposed
by Cassius' antithesis, ultimately to be replaced by a synthesis of both.
Hegel's interpretation of tragedy explicitly informs A. C. Bradley's emphasis
on "conflict or collision" in tragedy, in Oxford Lectures on
Poetry (69-95), which is the likely source of A. R. Humphreys' assertion
that Julius Caesar belongs to the category of "Hegelian
tragedy" (Oxford 7, 34).
3. History and Providence
43Romantic assumptions about both character and history
achieved their most magisterial expression early in the twentieth century in A.
C. Bradley's Shakespearean Tragedy, which effectively culminated the
Romantic tradition. Bradley attended to just four plays, Hamlet, Othello,
Lear, and Macbeth, so he had little to say about Julius Caesar,
but it was enough to register his view in the long-running debate about the
hero: Shakespearean tragedy "is pre-eminently the story of one person, the
'hero,'" and in Julius Caesar "Brutus is the 'hero'" (7).
Writing shortly after Bradley, M. W. MacCallum treated the three plays
Shakespeare derived from Plutarch in the vein of Bradley's character criticism,
though MacCallum struck a balance in the Romantic debate about the "hero"
of Julius Caesar by proposing a solution akin to Snider's. On one hand,
MacCallum agreed with those who thought the "spirit of Caesar" (TLN
800) is present from first to last (214), even when Julius Caesar himself is
not, and this "spirit," which eventually prevails in Octavius, the
future first emperor, is the Hegelian "spirit of Empire, the spirit of
practical greatness in the domains of war, policy, organisation" (241).
Brutus, on the other hand, is both "the model republican, the paragon of
private and civic virtue" (233) and "the spirit of loyalty to
duty" (241). Like Caesar, Brutus imperfectly represents the ideal he
stands for, and the gap between spirit and human embodiment accounts both for
personal inconsistencies on Caesar's and Brutus's parts and for Brutus's
ultimate failure.
44Coming at the end of a critical tradition, MacCallum was
easy to dismiss as old-fashioned and out of touch, as J. C. Maxwell made clear
in his mid-century summary of writing about the Roman plays (6). MacCallum
anticipated two major movements in twentieth-century criticism of Julius
Caesar, however, and for that alone he deserves acknowledgment. For one
thing, his perception of Caesar's place in history is consistent with a
critical tradition concerning Shakespeare, history, and politics that gathered
strength and endured well past the time of Maxwell's summary. MacCallum pointed
to two passages in North's translation of Plutarch that supported a
providentialist reading of Caesar's rise (215-16): Caesar represented "the
absolute state of a monarchy and sovereign lord to govern" Rome (Plutarch
493), and Caesar seemed to be a "merciful physician, whom God had ordained
of special grace to be governor of the empire of Rome and to set all things
again at quiet stay" (Plutarch 864). MacCallum was impressed with these
passages, because he thought they explained Shakespeare's view of Julius Caesar
as "the spirit of Empire." In retrospect, MacCallum's own historical
situation in the British Empire in the first decade of the twentieth century
(especially as an expatriate Scot in Australia) illuminates his reading of both
Plutarch and Julius Caesar better than North's providentialist
translation illuminates Shakespeare's play. Even the weaknesses that
Shakespeare invented for Caesar, MacCallum maintains, are "spots in the
sun." Shakespeare is not concerned with them but rather with "the
plenary inspiration of Caesar's life, the inspiration that made him an
instrument of Heaven and that was to bring peace and order to the world"
(230). The plenary inspiration that MacCallum identifies would seem to have as
much to do with the early twentieth-century British Empire and the Romantic
idea of destined national self-fulfillment as with Shakespeare's Julius
Caesar.
45MacCallum's notion that Caesar was a divine instrument in
history acquired increasing solidity in the first half of the twentieth
century. Writing at about the same time as MacCallum (though he published his
essay much later), F. C. Kolbe thought Julius Caesar embodied "some
high moral teaching" concerning "the conception which the Greeks
called Nemesis" (154). This conception involved "the
embodiment of divine wrath and jealousy" in history, manifesting itself
first in Brutus's reaction against Caesar's ambition and second in retribution
by Caesar's spirit (156). Kolbe was less enamored of Caesarian imperialism than
MacCallum, but Kolbe's providentialist reading of Julius Caesar
complements MacCallum's, and Kolbe finds a classical precedent for it. Both
imperialism and nemesis appear in Mark Hunter's essay, first read as a paper
shortly after the general strike of 1926 and possibly in reaction against it.
Shakespeare's attitude to politics, Hunter maintained, "was that of a
Tory, the term being understood in a sense highly honourable," and in
Shakespeare's plays "the principle which renders ordered society possible
is said to be, not liberty, but obedience" (110-11). "The principle
of the rule of the single person" was, for Shakespeare, "the norm of
all manner of earthly power" (119). Hunter takes a dim view both of
"the lower social orders" (117) in Julius Caesar and of those
who conspire against Caesar. Providence enters Hunter's argument in his
analysis of Antony "as the instrument of retributory nemesis" against
the assassins (139). J. E. Phillips acknowledged both MacCallum and Hunter in
outlining a theory of political order that Phillips thought Shakespeare shared
with his contemporaries. This theory involves "a stratified, integrated
political society in which all the parts function for the welfare of the whole
under the administration of a single, sovereign governor" (4). Violation
of this order inevitably results in political chaos, which Phillips argued is
what happens in Julius Caesar: "we see, in the successful
government of the title figure, the advantage of monarchy, and in the
disastrous consequences of his assassination the evils of multiple
sovereignty" (172). The assassins "function out of their degree and
do violence to the state by taking justice into their own hands" (176).
For Phillips, the "spirit of Caesar" is "the concept of unitary
sovereignty," and it becomes "the nemesis against which Brutus'
efforts, however highly motivated, are of no avail" (188).
46Perceptions of historical providentialism in Julius
Caesar that go back to MacCallum received their greatest impetus from E. M.
W. Tillyard's Shakespeare's History Plays in 1944. Tillyard was part of
an influential reaction against Romantic character criticism, turning instead
to the history of ideas and the presumed assumptions of Shakespeare's audience.
Still, Tillyard's continuity with MacCallum on some points is evident. Henry
VII and his dynasty fostered a "Tudor myth," Tillyard argued,
concerning their progenitor's accession and marriage to Elizabeth of York as
"the providential and happy ending of an organic piece of history"
(29). Tillyard thought the driving force behind this myth was a sense of
historical cause and effect that first appeared in the Tudor chronicler,
Polydore Vergil (35). Henry IV's violation of divinely appointed royal
rulership in his overthrow of Richard II more than a century before Henry VII's
accession was an originating cause that "shows the justice of God
punishing and working out the effects of a crime, till prosperity is
re-established in the Tudor monarchy" (36). A dynamic historical principle
thus complemented a static image of hierarchy, which Tillyard described with
copious contemporary references in The Elizabethan World Picture, also
published in 1944. The point of intersection for history and image was the idea
of order, the title of Chapter Two in The Elizabethan World Picture,
where Tillyard cites Ulysses' speech on "degree" in Troilus and
Cressida, as Phillips had done earlier (5-6). Order manifests itself both
in the smoothly running monarchy (including legitimate succession) and in the
obedience, deference, and degree of cosmic and political hierarchy. As Graham
Bradshaw notes (1-8), critics almost immediately pointed out that Tillyard
represented only the outlook of privileged power; in effect, as Hunter claimed
of Shakespeare himself, the attitude Tillyard described "was that of a
Tory." It is hard to imagine Tillyard assuming any other attitude at a
time when the British Empire was under severe strain from its conflict with
Nazi Germany and Japan.
47Though Tillyard had little to say about Julius Caesar,
his ideas soon became dominant in Shakespearean criticism, and their impact on
subsequent interpretation of Julius Caesar is evident. Citing Phillips (765n.
1), Brents Stirling outlined a case against Brutus based on "a flouting of
unitary sovereignty, that prime point of Tudor policy" (765). J. Leeds
Barroll brought enormous erudition to the task of showing that Shakespeare's
contemporaries inherited a tradition of seeing providence in Roman history in
much the same way they saw it in English history. Augustus' "beneficial
unification" of Rome after the civil wars was thus directly analogous to
"the Tudor myth itself" (328). Derek Traversi agreed that Shakespeare
saw "the necessity of order in public affairs" in both the English
history plays and the Roman plays, and Traversi thought that "this order
rests in some sense upon Caesar's exercise of power" (12). In Julius
Caesar in particular, "a tragic sacrifice" produces chaos and
mere calculation until "a new Roman order rises to replace that which has
been so wilfully destroyed" (21). Ernest Schanzer took a different view of
the play, but his view required him explicitly to reject the providentialist
reading, thereby confirming its importance in contemporary criticism by
default. Schanzer thought Julius Caesar was a "problem" play
because it focuses on a moral problem—namely, the sacrifice of "personal
loyalties" "to political ideals" (Problem 68). He therefore
disagreed that "the spirit of Caesar in the sense of 'Caesarism', the
absolute rule of a single man, informs the second part of the play" (35),
and he took issue with J. E. Phillips on this point in particular (36n. 1).
Believing that Julius Caesar is "one of Shakespeare's few genuine
problem plays" because it avoids "giving a plain and clear-cut
answer" to the problems it raises (70), Schanzer necessarily opposed the
moralism and providentialism of MacCallum, Tillyard, and others.
48The providentialist reading of Julius Caesar reached its
high-water mark in J. L. Simmons's book, Shakespeare's Pagan World.
Simmons argued that the plays derived from Plutarch "are more genuinely
Roman than is usually recognized" because they antedate Christian
revelation and therefore offer a genuinely "pagan world," devoid of
the moral clarity that one finds in the English history plays (7). Acknowledging
Barroll's essay for this view (8n. 21), Simmons traced it to the Augustinian
idea of history, which he thought was evident in Thomas North's translation of
North's Plutarch, specifically in the Epistle Dedicatory to Queen Elizabeth.
Simmons also acknowledged, however, that Augustine's view is not one of
providential triumphalism, and Simmons's reading of Julius Caesar
followed suit. Citing the same passages on providential Caesarism from North's
Plutarch that MacCallum had cited, Simmons argued that "practical politics
and providence" alike "urge the necessity of one-man rule" (72).
In other words, a strong man is necessary to prevent political chaos, but
Simmons offered minimal assent to the strong man himself, emphasizing both
Shakespeare's invented character weaknesses in Caesar and the play's sympathy
to Brutus. "The play develops a conflict between the good of Caesar
(political order, stability, and glory), flawed by his potential evil, and
Brutus's ideal of a world in which no Caesar is necessary, flawed by the nature
of man" (86). Simmons's complex and ironic analysis may respond to his own
historical context toward the end of the Vietnam war, and his emphasis on
Caesar's weaknesses tests the providential reading about as strongly as it could
be tested and still hold together. With the rise of new historicism and
cultural materialism in the next decade after Simmons's book appeared, reaction
against Tillyard in particular became so strong that providentialist
interpretations virtually disappeared from the critical record. John Drakakis's
introduction to the collection of essays called Alternative Shakespeares,
for example, explicitly challenged Tillyard (14-15), and Alessandro Serpieri's
analysis of Julius Caesar in that collection is entirely semiotic
(126-34).
4. Self-Deception
49The second point in which MacCallum anticipated
twentieth-century critical developments concerning Julius Caesar was his
recognizing strong inconsistency in the characters of both Caesar and
Brutus—inconsistency so strong that MacCallum referred to it as self-deception.
Noting Caesar's fear of supernatural signs, MacCallum acknowledges "a
touch of self-deception as well as of superstition in Caesar, and this
self-deception reappears in other more important matters," such as
Caesar's repeated insistence that he is not afraid (220-21). (Gervinus had
anticipated MacCallum on this point: Caesar "speaks so much of having no
fear, that by this very thing he betrays his fear" [720].) As for Brutus,
MacCallum thought he was "doubly duped, by his own subtlety and his own
simplicity in league with his conscientiousness . . . and such self-deception
avenges itself as surely as any intentional crime" (255). Despite these
canny insights, MacCallum was so impressed by Caesar's superiority as an
imperial ideal that he played down his own observation and understated the
extent to which Shakespeare had made Caesar and Brutus resemble one another.
50Though MacCallum was a neo-Romantic critic, his recognition
of self-deception resonates strongly with postmodern criticism, because
self-deception is a key expression of what Paul Ricoeur calls
"suspicion" in postmodern thinking. The formative thinkers for
postmodernism, Ricoeur points out, are Marx, Freud, and Nietzsche, who all
recognized a disjunction between conscious intention and unconscious
motivation, thereby challenging the emphasis on rational consciousness that had
prevailed in western thinking since Descartes ("I think, therefore I
am"). Marx called this disjunction "false consciousness," but
all three of Ricoeur's "masters of suspicion" acknowledged it in
various forms. Using Ricoeur's key word, "suspicion," in describing
Caesar's self-deception, MacCallum anticipates postmodern analysis when he
writes of Caesar that "if anything could make us suspicious, it would be
his constant harping on his flawless valour" (221). Paradoxically,
however, the most thoughtful expounders of self-deception in Shakespeare,
Stanley Cavell and Harry Berger, have not addressed Julius Caesar, and
the topic has been discussed since MacCallum principally in historical terms,
as a product of Shakespeare's reflection on neo-stoicism and skepticism.
51Passing references to self-deception are made by Brents
Stirling, who sees it as a characteristic of Brutus alone (765), and by R. A.
Foakes, who mentions it as one of many examples of things coming full circle in
such a way as to create unity among the play's diverse elements. Brutus's
"self-deception, an obsession with names and an ignorance of
reality," defeats his idealistic effort to find liberty from Caesar's
supposed bondage (270). But MacCallum's understatement of his own insight
concerning self-deception was most importantly corrected in an article by
Norman Rabkin, who was at the forefront of many postmodern developments in
Shakespearean criticism. Rabkin pointed out close parallels between two
consecutive scenes in Julius Caesar (2.1 and 2.2), with the argument
that Shakespeare invented the parallels in order to emphasize similarities
between Caesar and Brutus. Brutus's soliloquy in 2.1 shows "a capacity to
be deceived by analogies of his own making" (244), and Caesar's insistence
on his fearlessness in 2.2 "degenerates immediately from magnificence to
bluster, culminating in inflated self-adulation ironic in the context"
(245). A peculiar "balance of perception and self-righteous
blindness" is apparent in both men (246), and the point of their
"wishful self-deception" (249) is that "the spirit of
Caesar" is avenged in the destruction of its mirror image, so that the
play becomes, in effect, a revenge tragedy, in which Brutus's "crime
against established order" (251) is punished. (Foakes had also seen the
play "as a kind of revenge tragedy" in its cyclical character [263].)
Rabkin thus preserved a vestige of the providential reading, even referring to
"Nemesis" (251n. 11), while emphasizing an ironic reading of
character in Julius Caesar that would have been impossible for
MacCallum. In his revision of the essay for Shakespeare and the Common
Understanding, Rabkin identified Julius Caesar with the history
plays that precede it: "The tragedy of the historical plays is based
increasingly on Shakespeare's psychology, which sees human ideals and the
virtue of reason set hopelessly against the fact of the human drive for
power" (120).
52Acknowledging Rabkin (12) but moving in another direction
entirely, John Anson cited neo-stoicism in the 1590s to explain Shakespeare's
characterization of Caesar and Brutus in an anti-stoic manner, and Anson
emphasized the self-deception of Brutus in particular: "the love of
country that leads him to murder his dearest friend clearly serves to conceal
an envy of Caesar so great that he cannot afford to admit it. To do so would be
to admit that his whole sense of self was shadowed by an intolerable comparison
with Caesar" (25). Rene Fortin's emphasis on skepticism in Julius
Caesar is as strong as Rabkin's, and Fortin also focused on the play's most
noble characters, Caesar and Brutus, who are nonetheless "enveloped by the
mists of error, victims of deception and self-deception" (342). So
pervasive is the lack of self-knowledge that Shakespeare seems "to involve
the audience in the fallible judgments of the characters," so that the
play becomes "an exploration of man's epistemological situation" in
the manner of Montaigne (346). Marvin Vawter acknowledged Anson (173) but
focused exclusively on Brutus, because of Brutus's reputation as a stoic, which
Shakespeare acknowledges in Julius Caesar (TLN 2132-33, 2442). (For a
rebuttal to Vawter's argument about Brutus's stoicism, see Monsarrat, 139-44,
especially 141-42n. 2). For Vawter, the human situation in Julius Caesar
is not defined by skepticism, as it is for Fortin, but by the implicit
affirmation of "an inseparable composition of mind and body," and
Brutus errs in trying to espouse "the self-sufficiency of
virtue-reason" at the expense of his body (177). So severe is the
disjunction that Brutus is "unable to see himself" (180), and he
misjudges everyone, including himself: "his sick mind is brutalizing his
body with the result that there is nothing 'wholesome' about him" (181),
even though, ironically, "he believes himself incapable of misjudgment or
moral error" (188). Far from being a flawed nobleman, in Vawter's view,
Brutus is so deeply self-deceived that critical attempts to reserve a shred of
dignity for him are misguided (173).
The most perceptive discussion of
self-deception in Julius Caesar is by Geoffrey Miles, who is the play's
most careful historical critic. In an argument that bears some comparison to
Foakes's (267-68), Miles acknowledges that "my greatest debt is to
Simmons" (2n. 2), though he sets Simmons's providentialism aside and illuminates
Simmons's point that Shakespeare's Rome is a "world apart" by
emphasizing the distinctive interdependence of individual identity and social
identity—both emphatically "Roman." Miles proceeds by tracing two
traditions of stoic constancy, one Ciceronian and the other Senecan, that he
thinks are especially important in Shakespeare's Plutarchan plays. A
"flaw" in both traditions, Miles maintains, "is the failure of
self-knowledge" (138), which marks all the characters in Julius Caesar,
but especially Brutus. Though Brutus appeals to republican idealism, he
"seems unaware how far his decision to kill Caesar is motivated by
personal and family pride" (131-32). In other words, he is self-deceived
about his motives, and Miles draws an appropriate postmodern conclusion:
"The play has an almost Freudian sense of how emotion can work all the
more powerfully because it is repressed" (132).
5. Imagery
An important twentieth-century
development in criticism of Julius Caesar that MacCallum did not
anticipate is study of the play's imagery, which has also, like the study of
self-deception, been readily adapted to postmodern criticism. In this vein, the
first important name for Julius Caesar is G. Wilson Knight, though the
most influential critic of Shakespearean imagery was Caroline Spurgeon.
Eschewing character criticism, because "the 'character' cannot be
abstracted from those imaginative effects of poetry and poetic-drama of which
he is composed" (19), Knight nonetheless reinvented another Romantic
emphasis, which he called "imaginative interpretation" (1-31). He
believed that imagery is "essentially transmitted imaginatively to the
imaginative consciousness" (1), and he revived Schlegel's and Coleridge's
sense of organic form in asserting that "imaginative criticism judges rather
by results, by the tree's fruits, not its roots" (21). Distinguishing his
approach to imagery from Caroline Spurgeon's in a 1951 Preface, Knight noted
that Spurgeon had found Julius Caesar "poor in 'imagery,'"
whereas he thought "no single work of Shakespeare so tingles with vivid,
fiery and—to use Masefield's word—'startling' life" (viii). Taking a more
expansive view of imagery than Spurgeon, Knight introduced the idea of the
"theme" in close reading (1), an idea that would become influential
in New Criticism, and he traced a number of themes through Julius Caesar,
beginning with "animal-suggestion" (also noticed by Spurgeon but less
broadly) and "metals" (33).
Word association was important for
Knight, including associations between his own words to describe Julius
Caesar. He summarizes a long list of animal images, for example, as having
"a single quality: vivid and picturesque perception," and he links it
with metallic imagery through "the flash of metals" (34).
"Vivid" and "flash" both involve sight imagery, but the
imagery is Knight's, not Shakespeare's, and Knight does not relate it to
problems of seeing and perception that are pervasive in Julius Caesar,
presumably because they are a prominent part of the play's literal texture and
therefore do not appeal to the "imaginative consciousness."
Over-generalization and solipsism mark Knight's writing about imagery in
particular, though a characteristic inability to define "imagery" was
pointed out by Lillian Hornstein in an early critique of Spurgeon's book as
well. Nonetheless, Knight's observations are often acute, and his influence on
subsequent criticism is hard to overestimate. He is perceptive about
"body-references" (37-48), including eyes, ears, hair, lips, throat,
nourishment, sleeplessness, illness, and especially blood (45-48). Not
surprisingly, his summary of "all this imagery" is that it is
"all visual, vivid" (48), thus coming back to his own opening
generalization in a markedly impressionistic manner: "So we have a clear
train of ideas: man's body, visually, almost erotically, observed; thoughts of
physical weakness and sickness; emotion, blood, the heart's passion—the life
forces encased in the body; finally, spirit, fire, the fine essence of
vitality, the human spirit in all its resplendent power and beauty, housed as
it may be in a frail tenement of flesh" (53).
Leo Kirschbaum developed Knight's
remarks about the body in Julius Caesar in an essay on blood, though
Kirschbaum addressed staging rather than language. (Knight was an actor, as
well as a critic, and he insists that "stage representation" is
"necessary, where, if the production be careful and correct, the purely
imaginative effects of Shakespeare may be extremely powerful" [20], yet he
attends entirely to poetry, not to dramatic representation.) Noting that
Shakespeare's plays call for no less stage blood than those of his
contemporaries, Kirschbaum points out that bloody deeds in Julius Caesar
are "not metaphorical at all. They are naturalistic stage effects coram
populo deliberately meant by Shakespeare for actual production and
undoubtedly achieved at the Globe" (520). His primary example is Brutus's
urging the conspirators to bathe their hands in Caesar's blood after the
assassination—a bold and horrific scene that Shakespeare invented (523). Its
effect, Kirschbaum, argued, is to present in the most concrete possible way the
horror of Brutus's actual deed in contrast to the idealism with which he
undertakes it. Moreover, the blood that he smears on himself "is the symbol
and mark of the blood and destruction which is to flow through the rest of the
play" (524). The conspirators may drain the blood from Caesar's body, but
they are unable, as MacCallum and others had pointed out, to destroy his
vengeful spirit. Also focusing on Brutus's attempt "to dignify
assassination, the means, by lifting it to the level of rite and ceremony"
(765-66), Brents Stirling pursued an interpretative strategy closer to Knight's
than Kirschbaum's, finding "the theme of incantation and ritual" throughout
Julius Caesar as a structural principle (767). R. A. Foakes's essay is
also reminiscent of Knight's criticism, which Foakes acknowledges (259n. 3).
Raising a question about the play's "unity" at the outset, Foakes
answers it in a Romantic manner that is indebted to Knight, finding a
consistent theme in things coming full circle (260), but incidentally tracing
others "themes," such as blood, fire, and sickness.
57Building on Knight's and Kirschbaum's insistence that poetic
imagery and stage imagery complement each other in a play, Maurice Charney
focused on three "image themes" in Julius Caesar: storm,
blood, and fire (42). Each of these themes is ambiguous, he urged, because
their interpretation depends on whether one favors Caesar or the conspirators,
though the play favors neither one. Charney traced the "blood theme"
from its introduction in Brutus's conversation with Cassius in TLN 799
("Let's be sacrificers, but not butchers") to Titinius's lament for
Cassius in TLN 2545-48. Following Kirschbaum, Charney emphasized stage action,
pointing out that blood imagery keeps Caesar's assassination before the
audience by having Caesar's body on stage for most of 3.1 and 3.2, including
the "fearful blood ritual" in which Brutus leads the conspirators
(52). Blood and hunting dominate Antony's oration in such a way as to stress
"butchery rather than the sacrifice Brutus hoped for" before the
assassination (55). Cassius's death by the same sword that he used to kill
Caesar "is the reciprocity of blood for blood" (59).
58Two critics publishing simultaneously in Shakespeare
Studies took their discussion of Julius Caesar's imagery in the
direction of Elizabethan religion, prompted by Stirling's comments about ritual
in the play. Naomi Conn Liebler emphasized the possible influence of Plutarch's
Life of Romulus on Julius Caesar and on Shakespeare's way
of imagining the feast of Lupercal in particular, since Plutarch describes the
Lupercal in greater detail in Romulus than in any of his other
biographies. Where blood imagery is concerned, Liebler points out that
"the cutting up of the sacrificial pharmakos, whose blood is then
smeared upon the flesh of the priestly celebrants, is one of the central events
in the rites of the Lupercalia," and she compares the ritual to Brutus's
"insistence on the semblance of a ritual as a pattern for Caesar's
assassination" (183). Elizabethans would have responded to the ritual
aspects of Shakespeare's play, learned from Plutarch, because their own lives
were full of "Lupercalia-like rites" (189). David Kaula's
interpretation of religion in Julius Caesar addresses the reformation
context in particular. Adoration of Caesar in the play "is something akin
to Roman Catholic worship" (199), just as Cassius's satirical description
of Caesar's weaknesses is akin to Protestant attacks on the Pope (200). Blood
imagery makes Caesar "a redeemer who voluntarily sheds his blood for the
spiritual sustenance of his people," and Decius's crafty description of
Calpurnia's dream imagines Romans competing for "relics" of Caesar as
Catholics in England sought relics of their martyrs to Elizabeth's regime
(204-5). Following this train of thought, "we might even see a moderate
form of Protestantism reflected in Brutus's self-conscious Stoic virtue"
(206).
59The imagistic and thematic interpretation that Knight
introduced to criticism of Julius Caesar marked the heyday of New
Criticism in particular, from the 1930s to the 1970s. The movement was named
for John Crowe Ransom's book, published in 1941, but the method was practiced
in England as well, by Knight himself and especially by F. R. Leavis. New
Critics theorized a way of reading that eschewed literary history and the
history of ideas, practiced by critics like Tillyard, in favor of what W. K.
Wimsatt called "verbal icons," emphasizing "a verbal image which
fully realizes its verbal capacities," both pictorially and as "an
interpretation of reality in its metaphoric and symbolic dimensions" (x).
Cleanth Brooks declared that it is "heresy" "to refer the
structure of the poem . . . to something outside the poem," including
history (184). Despite its appeal for several decades, this way of reading eventually
ran its course as competing interpretations of the same kind increasingly
proliferated, suggesting that no standard could be applied for preferring one
reading over another. "My Theme Can Lick Your Theme" is the facetious
title of a serious article by Richard Levin on the circular reasoning of
thematic interpretation, when the thematic critic begins by assuming what he or
she is going to find in the text and then proceeds to find it. Levin's 1979
book effectively rang the death knell of thematic criticism for Julius
Caesar as Knight originally conceived it.
60With the advent of postmodern criticism in the 1980s,
however, the study of imagery took on new life and new forms. Postmodern
commentary on imagery of the body in Julius Caesar depends on a
perceived disjunction between conscious intention and unconscious motivation—a
disjunction that is frequently described in terms of a suspicious false
consciousness, as in the case of self-deception (discussed above). The
assumption of gender hierarchy (with male superior to female), for example,
often appears both consciously and unconsciously in writing from the past and
is often perpetuated in critical commentary about past writers, including
Shakespeare. Gail Kern Paster addressed this particular assumption in her
comments on blood imagery in Julius Caesar, pointing out that Mikhail
Bakhtin distinguishes "the grotesque, essentially medieval conception of
an unfinished, self-transgressing open body of hyperactive orifices" from
a "classical body" that is relatively complete, closed, and therefore
perceived as more nearly perfect (285). Paster argues that this distinction is
not only historical (early modern as opposed to medieval) but also gendered,
with the "open" body being female and the "closed" body
male. With this distinction in mind, she reads the body images of Julius
Caesar as a complex attempt on the conspirators' part to make Caesar female
(a vulnerable, bleeding body), countered by Antony's attempt to
"recuperate Caesar's body for his own political uses by redefining
Caesar's blood and Caesar's bleeding" (286). Paster draws on and
acknowledges Charney's and Kaula's essays in particular, but her emphasis and
interpretation are quite different from theirs—not to trace the workings of
Shakespeare's creative imagination but to find traces of unconscious
patriarchal bias in the play's language, imagery, and action. Paster affirms Kaula's
reading of Decius's reinterpretation of Calpurnia's dream, for example, as
influenced by the medieval cult of the Holy Blood (294), and she points out
that "Decius Brutus specifically allegorizes Caesar as a lactating
figure" by using the verb "suck" to describe the action of
Romans who gather for nourishment at Caesar's bloody fountain (295). This
strikingly original interpretation of blood imagery in Julius Caesar
opened up new possibilities of understanding the play, both textually and
historically.
61Writing at the same time as Paster, Mark Rose took blood
imagery in the direction of still another form of postmodern analysis, New
Historicism. Caesar's assassination is "conspicuously ritualized,"
Rose points out, in the conspirators' smearing of Caesar's blood on
themselves—a ceremony Brutus imagines being performed in future theaters
(298-99). Caesar's bloody death thus becomes the paradoxical basis of his
historic monumentality, which Shakespeare's play celebrates as "a kind of
political Mass"—a point Rose compares to Kaula's analysis of Caesar as a
political redeemer modeled on Christ (301). What Caesar redeems is Roman political
order, which he initiates as the de facto first emperor and the founder of an
imperial tradition that the Tudor monarchs frequently invoked as the basis of
their own authority (302). "Drained out of the official religion,"
Rose observes, "magic and ceremony reappeared not only on the stage, but
in the equally theatrical world of the court" (302). Though Rose seems
unaware of Stephen Greenblatt's essay on exorcism, first published five years
earlier, Rose's interpretation of the bleeding Caesar is fully compatible with
Greenblatt's ideas, which became the basis of New Historicism's positing of a
historical false consciousness about religion, art, and political power. The
Elizabethan theater was crucial, Greenblatt argues, in England's transition
from a sacred to a secular culture. Shakespeare's plays evoke sacred signs but
consistently secularize them in a form "drained" of
"institutional and doctrinal significance," so that "the
official position is emptied out, even as it is loyally confirmed"
(125-26). What had once been spiritually literal became merely literary, as the
culture took "a drastic swerve from the sacred to the secular—in the
theater" (126). Both Rose and Greenblatt use the image of
"draining" to describe late Elizabethan secularization; both see the
theater as crucial to the process; both see the process as unavoidably
political, given the theatricality of the court.
62In a complex argument that effectively combines feminism and
New Historicism, Coppèlia Kahn addresses the blood imagery of Julius Caesar
in the context of republican competitiveness, which Shakespeare calls
"emulation," both in Julius Caesar (TLN 1141) and in other
plays. False consciousness appears in the idealism that hides republican
emulation from those engaged in it, especially Brutus: "in their vision of
the republic, these patricians represent to themselves an imaginary conception
of their real relation to the Roman state" (86). But parallel false
consciousness also appears in the conception of the republic as "a
distinctively masculine sphere in which debate and action, the exercise of
reason and freedom, make men truly virile" (83). Moreover, Kahn compares
imagined Roman false consciousness to contemporary Elizabethan emulation at
court (92-93). Roman virtus thus defines republican virility over
against female submissiveness, and Kahn interprets the contrast in much the
same way as Paster. Portia's self-wounding is the oppositional counterpart to
the conspirators' wounding of Caesar: the first is a woman's attempt to imitate
a man's constancy (101), and the second "resoundingly feminizes
Caesar" (104), after Decius successfully construes Calpurnia's predictive
dream of the assassination as a nurturing image, which "recalls the legend
of Romulus and Remus who, suckled by the she-wolf, were thus enabled to found
the Roman state" (103). By attending carefully to both ancient Roman and
Elizabethan texts, Kahn freshly illuminates suspicion of power in Julius
Caesar where competitive Roman patricians and Elizabethan aristocrats are
both concerned.
No comments:
Post a Comment